Moritz Schlick (nonfiction): Difference between revisions
(Created page with "'''Friedrich Albert Moritz Schlick''' (/ʃlɪk/; German: [ʃlɪk] (About this soundlisten); April 14, 1882 – June 22, 1936) was a German philosopher, physicist, and the foun...") |
No edit summary |
||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
'''Friedrich Albert Moritz Schlick''' (/ʃlɪk/; German: [ʃlɪk] (About this soundlisten); April 14, 1882 – June 22, 1936) was a German philosopher, physicist, and the founding father of logical positivism and the Vienna Circle. | [[File:Moritz_Schlick.jpg|thumb|Moritz Schlick.]]'''Friedrich Albert Moritz Schlick''' (/ʃlɪk/; German: [ʃlɪk] (About this soundlisten); April 14, 1882 – June 22, 1936) was a German philosopher, physicist, and the founding father of logical positivism and the Vienna Circle. | ||
== Early life and works == | == Early life and works == | ||
Schlick was born in Berlin to a wealthy family. His father was Ernst Albert Schlick and his mother was Agnes Arndt. At the age of sixteen, he started to read Descartes' Meditations and Schopenhauer's ''Die beiden Grundprobleme der Ethik''. Especially ''Also sprach Zarathurstra'' (Thus Spoke Zarathustra) by Friedrich Nietzsche would impress him. | Schlick was born in Berlin to a wealthy family. His father was Ernst Albert Schlick and his mother was Agnes Arndt. At the age of sixteen, he started to read Descartes' Meditations and Schopenhauer's ''Die beiden Grundprobleme der Ethik''. Especially ''Also sprach Zarathurstra'' (Thus Spoke Zarathustra) by [[Friedrich Nietzsche (nonfiction)|Friedrich Nietzsche]] would impress him. | ||
He studied physics at the University of Heidelberg, the University of Lausanne, and, ultimately, the University of Berlin under Max Planck. Schlick explained this choice in his autobiography by saying that, despite his love for philosophy, he believed that only mathematical physics could help him obtain actual and exact knowledge. He felt deep distrust towards any metaphysical speculation. | He studied physics at the University of Heidelberg, the University of Lausanne, and, ultimately, the University of Berlin under [[Max Planck (nonfiction)|Max Planck]]. Schlick explained this choice in his autobiography by saying that, despite his love for philosophy, he believed that only mathematical physics could help him obtain actual and exact knowledge. He felt deep distrust towards any metaphysical speculation. | ||
In 1904, he completed his PhD thesis at the University of Berlin, ''Über die Reflexion des Lichts in einer inhomogenen Schicht'' (On the Reflection of Light in a Non-Homogeneous Medium). After a year as Privatdozent at Göttingen, he turned to the study of Philosophy in Zurich. In 1907, he married Blanche Hardy. In 1908, he published Lebensweisheit (The Wisdom of Life), a slim volume about eudaemonism, the theory that happiness results from the pursuit of personal fulfillment as opposed to passing pleasures. | In 1904, he completed his PhD thesis at the University of Berlin, ''Über die Reflexion des Lichts in einer inhomogenen Schicht'' ("On the Reflection of Light in a Non-Homogeneous Medium"). After a year as Privatdozent at Göttingen, he turned to the study of Philosophy in Zurich. In 1907, he married [[Blanche Hardy (nonfiction)|Blanche Hardy]]. In 1908, he published ''Lebensweisheit'' ("The Wisdom of Life"), a slim volume about eudaemonism, the theory that happiness results from the pursuit of personal fulfillment as opposed to passing pleasures. | ||
His habilitation thesis at the University of Rostock, ''Das Wesen der Wahrheit nach der modernen Logik'' (The Nature of Truth According to Modern Logic), was published in 1910. Several essays about aesthetics followed, whereupon Schlick turned his attention to problems of epistemology, the philosophy of science, and more general questions about science. In this last category, Schlick distinguished himself by publishing a paper in 1915 about Einstein's special theory of relativity, a topic only ten years old. He also published ''Raum und Zeit in der gegenwärtigen Physik'' (Space and Time in Contemporary Physics), which extended his earlier results by applying Poincaré's geometric conventionalism to explain Einstein's adoption of a non-Euclidean geometry in the general theory of relativity. | His habilitation thesis at the University of Rostock, ''Das Wesen der Wahrheit nach der modernen Logik'' ("The Nature of Truth According to Modern Logic"), was published in 1910. Several essays about aesthetics followed, whereupon Schlick turned his attention to problems of epistemology, the philosophy of science, and more general questions about science. In this last category, Schlick distinguished himself by publishing a paper in 1915 about Einstein's special theory of relativity, a topic only ten years old. He also published ''Raum und Zeit in der gegenwärtigen Physik'' ("Space and Time in Contemporary Physics"), which extended his earlier results by applying [[Henri Poincaré (nonfiction)|Henri Poincaré]]'s geometric conventionalism to explain [[Albert Einstein (nonfiction)|Albert Einstein]]'s adoption of a non-Euclidean geometry in the general theory of relativity. | ||
== The Vienna Circle and Wittgenstein == | == The Vienna Circle and Wittgenstein == | ||
After early appointments at Rostock and Kiel, in 1922 Schlick assumed the chair of Naturphilosophie at the University of Vienna which had previously been held by Ludwig Boltzmann and Ernst Mach. Schlick displayed an unusual success in organizing talented individuals in the philosophical and scientific spheres. When Schlick arrived in Vienna, he was invited to lead a group of scientists and philosophers who met regularly (on Thursday evenings in the Chemistry Building) to discuss philosophical topics in the sciences. Early members included the mathematician Hans Hahn and, within a few years, they were joined by Rudolf Carnap, Herbert Feigl, Kurt Gödel, Otto Neurath, Friedrich Waismann and others. They initially called themselves the Ernst Mach Association, but they eventually became best known as the Vienna Circle. In the years 1925–26, the Thursday night group discussed recent work in the foundations of mathematics by Gottlob Frege, Bertrand Russell, and Ludwig Wittgenstein. Wittgenstein's book, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, was a work that advanced, among other things, a logical theory of symbolism and a "picture" or "model" theory of language. Schlick and his group were impressed by the work, devoting considerable time to its study and, even when it was no longer the principal focus of their discussion, it was mentioned in discussion. Eventually Wittgenstein agreed to meet with Schlick and other Circle members to discuss the Tractatus and other ideas but he later found it necessary to restrict the visitors to sympathetic interlocutors. Through Schlick's influence, Wittgenstein was encouraged to consider a return to philosophy after some ten years away from the field. Schlick and Waismann's discussions with Wittgenstein continued until the latter felt that germinal ideas had been used without permission in an essay by Carnap, a charge of dubious merit. But he continued discussions in letters to Schlick after he no longer met with other Circle members. | After early appointments at Rostock and Kiel, in 1922 Schlick assumed the chair of Naturphilosophie at the University of Vienna which had previously been held by [[Ludwig Boltzmann (nonfiction)|Ludwig Boltzmann]] and [[Ernst Mach (nonfiction)|Ernst Mach]]. Schlick displayed an unusual success in organizing talented individuals in the philosophical and scientific spheres. When Schlick arrived in Vienna, he was invited to lead a group of scientists and philosophers who met regularly (on Thursday evenings in the Chemistry Building) to discuss philosophical topics in the sciences. Early members included the mathematician Hans Hahn and, within a few years, they were joined by [[Rudolf Carnap (nonfiction)|Rudolf Carnap]], [[Herbert Feigl (nonfiction)|Herbert Feigl]], [[Kurt Gödel (nonfiction)|Kurt Gödel]], [[Otto Neurath (nonfiction)|Otto Neurath]], [[Friedrich Waismann (nonfiction)|Friedrich Waismann]], and others. They initially called themselves the Ernst Mach Association, but they eventually became best known as the Vienna Circle. In the years 1925–26, the Thursday night group discussed recent work in the foundations of mathematics by [[Gottlob Frege (nonfiction)|Gottlob Frege]], [[Bertrand Russell (nonfiction)|Bertrand Russell]], and [[Ludwig Wittgenstein (nonfiction)|Ludwig Wittgenstein]]. Wittgenstein's book, ''Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus'', was a work that advanced, among other things, a logical theory of symbolism and a "picture" or "model" theory of language. Schlick and his group were impressed by the work, devoting considerable time to its study and, even when it was no longer the principal focus of their discussion, it was mentioned in discussion. Eventually Wittgenstein agreed to meet with Schlick and other Circle members to discuss the ''Tractatus'' and other ideas but he later found it necessary to restrict the visitors to sympathetic interlocutors. Through Schlick's influence, Wittgenstein was encouraged to consider a return to philosophy after some ten years away from the field. Schlick and Waismann's discussions with Wittgenstein continued until the latter felt that germinal ideas had been used without permission in an essay by Carnap, a charge of dubious merit. But he continued discussions in letters to Schlick after he no longer met with other Circle members. | ||
== General Theory of Knowledge and later works == | == General Theory of Knowledge and later works == | ||
Schlick had worked on his ''Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre'' (General Theory of Knowledge) between 1918 and 1925, and, though later developments in his philosophy were to make various contentions of his epistemology untenable, the General Theory is perhaps his greatest work in its acute reasoning against synthetic a priori knowledge. This critique of synthetic a priori knowledge argues that the only truths which are self-evident to reason are statements which are true as a matter of definition, such as the statements of formal logic and mathematics. The truth of all other statements must be evaluated with reference to empirical evidence. If a statement is proposed which is not a matter of definition, and not capable of being confirmed or falsified by evidence, that statement is "metaphysical", which is synonymous with "meaningless", or "nonsense". This is the principle upon which members of the Vienna Circle were most clearly in agreement — with each other, as well as with Wittgenstein. | Schlick had worked on his ''Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre'' (General Theory of Knowledge) between 1918 and 1925, and, though later developments in his philosophy were to make various contentions of his epistemology untenable, the General Theory is perhaps his greatest work in its acute reasoning against synthetic ''a priori'' knowledge. This critique of synthetic a priori knowledge argues that the only truths which are self-evident to reason are statements which are true as a matter of definition, such as the statements of formal logic and mathematics. The truth of all other statements must be evaluated with reference to empirical evidence. If a statement is proposed which is not a matter of definition, and not capable of being confirmed or falsified by evidence, that statement is "metaphysical", which is synonymous with "meaningless", or "nonsense". This is the principle upon which members of the Vienna Circle were most clearly in agreement — with each other, as well as with Wittgenstein. | ||
== Problems of Ethics == | == Problems of Ethics == | ||
Between 1926 and 1930, Schlick labored to finish Fragen der Ethik (Problems of Ethics | Between 1926 and 1930, Schlick labored to finish ''Fragen der Ethik'' ("Problems of Ethics"), in which he surprised some of his fellow Circlists by including ethics as a viable branch of philosophy. In his 1932-33 contribution to ''Erkenntnis'', "Positivism and Realism", Schlick offered one of the most illuminating definitions of positivism as every view "which denies the possibility of metaphysics" (Schlick [1932-1933], p. 260). Accordingly he defined metaphysics as the doctrine of “true being”, “thing in itself” or “transcendental being”, a doctrine which obviously "presupposes that a non-true, lesser or apparent being stands opposed to it" (Ibid). Therefore in this work he bases the positivism on a kind of epistemology which holds that the only true beings are givens or constituents of experience. Also during this time, the Vienna Circle published The Scientific View of the World: The Vienna Circle as a homage to Schlick. Its strong anti-metaphysical stance crystallized the viewpoint of the group. | ||
Carnap, in his book Logical Syntax of Language, included a comment by Schlick on Wittgenstein 's Tractatus | Carnap, in his book ''[[Logical Syntax of Language (nonfiction)|Logical Syntax of Language]]'', included a comment by Schlick on Wittgenstein 's ''Tractatus'': | ||
<blockquote>Schlick ( [Wende] p.8 ) interprets Wittgenstein's position as follows: philosophy "is that activity by which the meaning of propositions is established or discovered" ; it is a question of "what the propositions actually mean. The content, soul, and spirit of science naturally consist in what is ultimately meant by its sentences; the philosophical activity of rendering significant is thus the alpha and omega of all scientific knowledge". | <blockquote>Schlick ( [Wende] p.8 ) interprets Wittgenstein's position as follows: philosophy "is that activity by which the meaning of propositions is established or discovered" ; it is a question of "what the propositions actually mean. The content, soul, and spirit of science naturally consist in what is ultimately meant by its sentences; the philosophical activity of rendering significant is thus the alpha and omega of all scientific knowledge". | ||
Line 32: | Line 32: | ||
== Schlick's murder == | == Schlick's murder == | ||
With the rise of the Nazis in Germany and Austrofascism in Austria, many of the Vienna Circle's members left for the United States and the United Kingdom. Schlick, however, stayed on at the University of Vienna. When visited by Herbert Feigl in 1935, he expressed dismay at events in Germany. On June 22, 1936, Schlick was ascending the steps of the university for a class when he was confronted by a former student, Johann Nelböck, who killed Schlick with a pistol. The court declared Nelböck to be fully compos mentis; he confessed to the act, and was detained without any resistance, but was unrepentant. The delinquent used the judicial proceedings as a chance to present himself and his ideology in the public. He claimed that Schlick's anti-metaphysical philosophy had "interfered with his moral restraint". In another version of the events, the murderer covered up all political causes and claimed that he was motivated by jealousy over his failed attachment to the female student Sylvia Borowicka, leading to a paranoid delusion about Schlick as his rival and persecutor. Nelböck was tried and sentenced, but the event became a distorted cause célèbre around which crystallized the growing nationalist and anti-Jewish sentiments in the city. (The fact that Schlick was not Jewish did not seem to matter to propagandists capitalizing on the crime.) After the annexation of Austria into Nazi Germany in 1938 the assassin was released on probation after serving two years of a 10-year sentence. | With the rise of the Nazis in Germany and Austrofascism in Austria, many of the Vienna Circle's members left for the United States and the United Kingdom. Schlick, however, stayed on at the University of Vienna. When visited by [[Herbert Feigl (nonfiction)|Herbert Feigl]] in 1935, he expressed dismay at events in Germany. On June 22, 1936, Schlick was ascending the steps of the university for a class when he was confronted by a former student, [[Johann Nelböck (nonfiction)|Johann Nelböck]], who killed Schlick with a pistol. The court declared Nelböck to be fully ''compos mentis''; he confessed to the act, and was detained without any resistance, but was unrepentant. The delinquent used the judicial proceedings as a chance to present himself and his ideology in the public. He claimed that Schlick's anti-metaphysical philosophy had "interfered with his moral restraint". In another version of the events, the murderer covered up all political causes and claimed that he was motivated by jealousy over his failed attachment to the female student [[Sylvia Borowicka (nonfiction)|Sylvia Borowicka]], leading to a paranoid delusion about Schlick as his rival and persecutor. Nelböck was tried and sentenced, but the event became a distorted ''cause célèbre'' around which crystallized the growing nationalist and anti-Jewish sentiments in the city. (The fact that Schlick was not Jewish did not seem to matter to propagandists capitalizing on the crime.) After the annexation of Austria into Nazi Germany in 1938 the assassin was released on probation after serving two years of a 10-year sentence. | ||
== Legacy == | == Legacy == | ||
Line 43: | Line 43: | ||
Works | Works | ||
Lebensweisheit. Versuch einer Glückseligkeitslehre. Munich, Becksche Verlagsbuchhandlung 1908[14] | * Lebensweisheit. Versuch einer Glückseligkeitslehre. Munich, Becksche Verlagsbuchhandlung 1908[14] | ||
Das Wesen der Wahrheit nach der modernen Logik, in: Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie und Soziologie, Jg. 34, 1910, p. 386-477 | * Das Wesen der Wahrheit nach der modernen Logik, in: Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie und Soziologie, Jg. 34, 1910, p. 386-477 | ||
Die philosophische Bedeutung des Relativitätsprinzips, in: Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 159, 1915, S. 129-175 | Die philosophische Bedeutung des Relativitätsprinzips, in: Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 159, 1915, S. 129-175 | ||
Raum und Zeit in der gegenwärtigen Physik. Berlin: Verlag von Julius Springer 1917 (4th ed. 1922) | * Raum und Zeit in der gegenwärtigen Physik. Berlin: Verlag von Julius Springer 1917 (4th ed. 1922) | ||
Hermann von Helmholtz. Schriften zur Erkenntnistheorie (Publishers: Moritz Schlick & Paul Hertz). Berlin: Springer 1921[15] | * Hermann von Helmholtz. Schriften zur Erkenntnistheorie (Publishers: Moritz Schlick & Paul Hertz). Berlin: Springer 1921[15] | ||
Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre. Berlin: Verlag von Julius Springer 1918 (2nd edition 1925)[16] | * Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre. Berlin: Verlag von Julius Springer 1918 (2nd edition 1925)[16] | ||
Kritizistische oder empiristische Deutung der neuen Physik?, in: Kant-Studien, 26, 1921, p. 96-111[17] | * Kritizistische oder empiristische Deutung der neuen Physik?, in: Kant-Studien, 26, 1921, p. 96-111[17] | ||
Einsteins Relativitätstheorie. In: Mosse Almanach, 1921, S. 105-123.[18][19] | * Einsteins Relativitätstheorie. In: Mosse Almanach, 1921, S. 105-123.[18][19] | ||
Erleben, Erkennen, Metaphysik, in: Kant-Studien, 31, 1926, p. 146-158[20] | * Erleben, Erkennen, Metaphysik, in: Kant-Studien, 31, 1926, p. 146-158[20] | ||
Vom Sinn des Lebens, in: Symposion. Philosophische Zeitschrift für Forschung und Aussprache, Jg. 1, 1927, p. 331-354[21] | Vom Sinn des Lebens, in: Symposion. Philosophische Zeitschrift für Forschung und Aussprache, Jg. 1, 1927, p. 331-354[21] | ||
Fragen der Ethik. Vienna: Verlag von Julius Springer 1930[14] | * Fragen der Ethik. Vienna: Verlag von Julius Springer 1930[14] | ||
Gibt es ein Materiales Apriori?, 1930 | Gibt es ein Materiales Apriori?, 1930 | ||
"Die Wende der Philosophie". Erkenntnis. 1: 4–11. 1930. doi:10.1007/BF00208605. | * "Die Wende der Philosophie". Erkenntnis. 1: 4–11. 1930. doi:10.1007/BF00208605. | ||
"Über das Fundament der Erkenntnis". Erkenntnis. 4: 79–99. 1934. doi:10.1007/BF01793485. | * "Über das Fundament der Erkenntnis". Erkenntnis. 4: 79–99. 1934. doi:10.1007/BF01793485. | ||
Unanswerable Questions, 1935 | * Unanswerable Questions, 1935 | ||
Meaning and Verification, 1936 | * Meaning and Verification, 1936 | ||
Gesammelte Aufsätze 1926-1936. Vienna: Gerold & Co. 1938 | * Gesammelte Aufsätze 1926-1936. Vienna: Gerold & Co. 1938 | ||
Die Probleme der Philosophie in ihrem Zusammenhang. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Verlag 1986 | * Die Probleme der Philosophie in ihrem Zusammenhang. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Verlag 1986 | ||
Moritz Schlick Gesamtausgabe. Vienna/New York: Springer Verlag 2006. — Almost complete author copy of Vol. I/1, I/2, I/3, I/5, I/6 | * Moritz Schlick Gesamtausgabe. Vienna/New York: Springer Verlag 2006. — Almost complete author copy of Vol. I/1, I/2, I/3, I/5, I/6 | ||
Notes | |||
== Notes == | |||
** Ted Poston, "Foundationalism" (Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy) | |||
* Hans Günther Ruß, Wissenschaftstheorie, Erkenntnistheorie und die Suche nach Wahrheit. Stuttgart, Kohlhammer Verlag 2004, p. 71. | |||
* Thomas Oberdan, Protocols, Truth and Convention, Rodopi, 1993, p. 110. | |||
* B. F. McGuinness (2013). Moritz Schlick. pp. 336–7. Once again, one has to understand Schlick's world conception, which he took over from Schopenhauer's world as representation and as will. … “To will something” – and here Schlick is heavily influenced by Schopenhauer – | |||
* Schlick, Moritz; Stadler; Wendel (2009). Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre. 1 (Kritische Gesamtausgabe ed.). Germany: Springer-Verlag. ISBN 978-3-211-32768-5. | |||
* Biography Archived 2016-03-04 at the Wayback Machine at Vienna University | |||
* Erkenntnis vol. 3, 1932/33. English: translated by David Rynin (PDF). Retrieved 2013-03-11. | |||
* Stadler, Friedrich (2001). Documentation: The Murder of Moritz Schlick, in: Friedrich Stadler (ed.). The Vienna Circle. Studies in the Origins, Development, and Influence of Logical Empiricism. Vienna, New York: Springer. pp. 866–909. ISBN 978-3-211-83243-1. | |||
* Silverman, Lisa (2012). Becoming Austrians: Jews and culture between the World Wars. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 60–65. ISBN 978-0-19-979484-3. | |||
* Lotz-Rimbach, Renata (2009). Mord verjaehrt nicht: Psychogramm eines politischen Mordes, in: Friedrich Stadler, Fynn Ole Engler (eds.). Stationen: dem Philosophen und Physiker Moritz Schlick zum 125. Geburtstag. Vienna, New York: Springer. pp. 81–104. ISBN 978-3-211-71580-2. | |||
* Csendes, Peter (2006). Wien: Von 1790 bis zur Gegenwart. Vol. 3. Vienna: Boehlau. pp. 499f. ISBN 978-3-205-99268-4. | |||
* Stadler, Friedrich (1997). Die andere Kulturgeschichte am Beispiel von Emigration und Exil der oesterreichischen Intellektuellen 1930-1940, in: Rolf Steininger, Michael Gehler (eds.). Oesterreich im 20. Jahrhundert. Ein Studienbuch in zwei Baenden. Von der Monarchie bis zum Zweiten Weltkrieg. Wien, Köln, Weimar: Boehlau. pp. 535–553. ISBN 978-3-205-98310-1. | |||
* Malina, Peter (1988). Tatort: Philosophenstiege, in: Michael Benedikt, Rudolf Burger (eds.). Bewusstsein, Sprache und Kunst. Vienna: Boehlau. pp. 231–253. | |||
* Reprinted in Vol. I/3 of the Moritz Schlick Gesamtausgabe | |||
* Editors' preface reprinted in Vol. I/5 of the Moritz Schlick Gesamtausgabe, p.255-264 | |||
* Reprinted as Vol. I/1 of the Moritz Schlick Gesamtausgabe | |||
* Reprinted in Vol. I/5 of the Moritz Schlick Gesamtausgabe, p.223-250 | |||
* Contribution to a competition of Scientific American; for background information see p.31ff in: Fynn Ole Engler, Moritz Schlick und Albert Einstein, MPI for the History of Science, 2006 | |||
* Reprinted in Vol. I/5 of the Moritz Schlick Gesamtausgabe, p.157-178 | |||
* Reprinted in Vol. I/6 of the Moritz Schlick Gesamtausgabe, p.33-56 | |||
References | * Reprinted in Vol. I/6 of the Moritz Schlick Gesamtausgabe, p.99-128 | ||
Edmonds, David and John Eidinow. Wittgenstein's Poker. New York: HarperCollins, 2001. | |||
Fynn Ole Engler, Mathias Iven. Moritz Schlick. Leben, Werk und Wirkung. Berlin: Parerga 2008. (in German) | == References == | ||
Schlick, Moritz. Positivism and Realism. Originally appeared in Erkenntnis 111 (1932/33); translated by Peter Heath and reprinted in Moritz Schlick: Philosophical Papers, Volume II (1925–1936) from Vienna Circle Collection, edited by Henk L. Mulder (Kluwer, 1979), pp. 259–284. | |||
Further reading | * Edmonds, David and John Eidinow. Wittgenstein's Poker. New York: HarperCollins, 2001. | ||
Holt, Jim, "Positive Thinking" (review of Karl Sigmund, Exact Thinking in Demented Times: The Vienna Circle and the Epic Quest for the Foundations of Science, Basic Books, 449 pp.), The New York Review of Books, vol. LXIV, no. 20 (21 December 2017), pp. 74–76. | * Fynn Ole Engler, Mathias Iven. Moritz Schlick. Leben, Werk und Wirkung. Berlin: Parerga 2008. (in German) | ||
External links | * Schlick, Moritz. Positivism and Realism. Originally appeared in Erkenntnis 111 (1932/33); translated by Peter Heath and reprinted in Moritz Schlick: * Philosophical Papers, Volume II (1925–1936) from Vienna Circle Collection, edited by Henk L. Mulder (Kluwer, 1979), pp. 259–284. | ||
== Further reading == | |||
* Holt, Jim, "Positive Thinking" (review of Karl Sigmund, Exact Thinking in Demented Times: The Vienna Circle and the Epic Quest for the Foundations of Science, Basic Books, 449 pp.), The New York Review of Books, vol. LXIV, no. 20 (21 December 2017), pp. 74–76. | |||
Schlick : Epistemology and Modern Physics | |||
Moritz Schlick research department at Rostock University | == External links == | ||
* [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Moritz_Schlick#Schlick's_murder Moritz Schlick] @ Wikipedia | |||
* Schlick : Epistemology and Modern Physics | |||
* Moritz Schlick research department at Rostock University |
Latest revision as of 09:53, 14 April 2020
Friedrich Albert Moritz Schlick (/ʃlɪk/; German: [ʃlɪk] (About this soundlisten); April 14, 1882 – June 22, 1936) was a German philosopher, physicist, and the founding father of logical positivism and the Vienna Circle.
Early life and works
Schlick was born in Berlin to a wealthy family. His father was Ernst Albert Schlick and his mother was Agnes Arndt. At the age of sixteen, he started to read Descartes' Meditations and Schopenhauer's Die beiden Grundprobleme der Ethik. Especially Also sprach Zarathurstra (Thus Spoke Zarathustra) by Friedrich Nietzsche would impress him.
He studied physics at the University of Heidelberg, the University of Lausanne, and, ultimately, the University of Berlin under Max Planck. Schlick explained this choice in his autobiography by saying that, despite his love for philosophy, he believed that only mathematical physics could help him obtain actual and exact knowledge. He felt deep distrust towards any metaphysical speculation.
In 1904, he completed his PhD thesis at the University of Berlin, Über die Reflexion des Lichts in einer inhomogenen Schicht ("On the Reflection of Light in a Non-Homogeneous Medium"). After a year as Privatdozent at Göttingen, he turned to the study of Philosophy in Zurich. In 1907, he married Blanche Hardy. In 1908, he published Lebensweisheit ("The Wisdom of Life"), a slim volume about eudaemonism, the theory that happiness results from the pursuit of personal fulfillment as opposed to passing pleasures.
His habilitation thesis at the University of Rostock, Das Wesen der Wahrheit nach der modernen Logik ("The Nature of Truth According to Modern Logic"), was published in 1910. Several essays about aesthetics followed, whereupon Schlick turned his attention to problems of epistemology, the philosophy of science, and more general questions about science. In this last category, Schlick distinguished himself by publishing a paper in 1915 about Einstein's special theory of relativity, a topic only ten years old. He also published Raum und Zeit in der gegenwärtigen Physik ("Space and Time in Contemporary Physics"), which extended his earlier results by applying Henri Poincaré's geometric conventionalism to explain Albert Einstein's adoption of a non-Euclidean geometry in the general theory of relativity.
The Vienna Circle and Wittgenstein
After early appointments at Rostock and Kiel, in 1922 Schlick assumed the chair of Naturphilosophie at the University of Vienna which had previously been held by Ludwig Boltzmann and Ernst Mach. Schlick displayed an unusual success in organizing talented individuals in the philosophical and scientific spheres. When Schlick arrived in Vienna, he was invited to lead a group of scientists and philosophers who met regularly (on Thursday evenings in the Chemistry Building) to discuss philosophical topics in the sciences. Early members included the mathematician Hans Hahn and, within a few years, they were joined by Rudolf Carnap, Herbert Feigl, Kurt Gödel, Otto Neurath, Friedrich Waismann, and others. They initially called themselves the Ernst Mach Association, but they eventually became best known as the Vienna Circle. In the years 1925–26, the Thursday night group discussed recent work in the foundations of mathematics by Gottlob Frege, Bertrand Russell, and Ludwig Wittgenstein. Wittgenstein's book, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, was a work that advanced, among other things, a logical theory of symbolism and a "picture" or "model" theory of language. Schlick and his group were impressed by the work, devoting considerable time to its study and, even when it was no longer the principal focus of their discussion, it was mentioned in discussion. Eventually Wittgenstein agreed to meet with Schlick and other Circle members to discuss the Tractatus and other ideas but he later found it necessary to restrict the visitors to sympathetic interlocutors. Through Schlick's influence, Wittgenstein was encouraged to consider a return to philosophy after some ten years away from the field. Schlick and Waismann's discussions with Wittgenstein continued until the latter felt that germinal ideas had been used without permission in an essay by Carnap, a charge of dubious merit. But he continued discussions in letters to Schlick after he no longer met with other Circle members.
General Theory of Knowledge and later works
Schlick had worked on his Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre (General Theory of Knowledge) between 1918 and 1925, and, though later developments in his philosophy were to make various contentions of his epistemology untenable, the General Theory is perhaps his greatest work in its acute reasoning against synthetic a priori knowledge. This critique of synthetic a priori knowledge argues that the only truths which are self-evident to reason are statements which are true as a matter of definition, such as the statements of formal logic and mathematics. The truth of all other statements must be evaluated with reference to empirical evidence. If a statement is proposed which is not a matter of definition, and not capable of being confirmed or falsified by evidence, that statement is "metaphysical", which is synonymous with "meaningless", or "nonsense". This is the principle upon which members of the Vienna Circle were most clearly in agreement — with each other, as well as with Wittgenstein.
Problems of Ethics
Between 1926 and 1930, Schlick labored to finish Fragen der Ethik ("Problems of Ethics"), in which he surprised some of his fellow Circlists by including ethics as a viable branch of philosophy. In his 1932-33 contribution to Erkenntnis, "Positivism and Realism", Schlick offered one of the most illuminating definitions of positivism as every view "which denies the possibility of metaphysics" (Schlick [1932-1933], p. 260). Accordingly he defined metaphysics as the doctrine of “true being”, “thing in itself” or “transcendental being”, a doctrine which obviously "presupposes that a non-true, lesser or apparent being stands opposed to it" (Ibid). Therefore in this work he bases the positivism on a kind of epistemology which holds that the only true beings are givens or constituents of experience. Also during this time, the Vienna Circle published The Scientific View of the World: The Vienna Circle as a homage to Schlick. Its strong anti-metaphysical stance crystallized the viewpoint of the group.
Carnap, in his book Logical Syntax of Language, included a comment by Schlick on Wittgenstein 's Tractatus:
Schlick ( [Wende] p.8 ) interprets Wittgenstein's position as follows: philosophy "is that activity by which the meaning of propositions is established or discovered" ; it is a question of "what the propositions actually mean. The content, soul, and spirit of science naturally consist in what is ultimately meant by its sentences; the philosophical activity of rendering significant is thus the alpha and omega of all scientific knowledge".
— Carnap, p.284, Logical Syntax of Language
Schlick's murder
With the rise of the Nazis in Germany and Austrofascism in Austria, many of the Vienna Circle's members left for the United States and the United Kingdom. Schlick, however, stayed on at the University of Vienna. When visited by Herbert Feigl in 1935, he expressed dismay at events in Germany. On June 22, 1936, Schlick was ascending the steps of the university for a class when he was confronted by a former student, Johann Nelböck, who killed Schlick with a pistol. The court declared Nelböck to be fully compos mentis; he confessed to the act, and was detained without any resistance, but was unrepentant. The delinquent used the judicial proceedings as a chance to present himself and his ideology in the public. He claimed that Schlick's anti-metaphysical philosophy had "interfered with his moral restraint". In another version of the events, the murderer covered up all political causes and claimed that he was motivated by jealousy over his failed attachment to the female student Sylvia Borowicka, leading to a paranoid delusion about Schlick as his rival and persecutor. Nelböck was tried and sentenced, but the event became a distorted cause célèbre around which crystallized the growing nationalist and anti-Jewish sentiments in the city. (The fact that Schlick was not Jewish did not seem to matter to propagandists capitalizing on the crime.) After the annexation of Austria into Nazi Germany in 1938 the assassin was released on probation after serving two years of a 10-year sentence.
Legacy
Schlick's enduring contribution to the world of philosophy is as the fount of logical positivism. His humanity, good will, gentleness, and especially his encouragement have been documented by many of his peers. Herbert Feigl and Albert Blumberg, in their introduction to the General Theory of Knowledge, wrote,
No other thinker was so well prepared to give new impetus to the philosophical questings of the younger generation. Though many of his students and successors have attained a higher degree of exactitude and adequacy in their logical analyses of problems in the theory of knowledge, Schlick had an unsurpassed sense for what is essential in philosophical issues.
— Feigl and Blumberg, Introduction, General Theory of Knowledge, p. xxi Works
- Lebensweisheit. Versuch einer Glückseligkeitslehre. Munich, Becksche Verlagsbuchhandlung 1908[14]
- Das Wesen der Wahrheit nach der modernen Logik, in: Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie und Soziologie, Jg. 34, 1910, p. 386-477
Die philosophische Bedeutung des Relativitätsprinzips, in: Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 159, 1915, S. 129-175
- Raum und Zeit in der gegenwärtigen Physik. Berlin: Verlag von Julius Springer 1917 (4th ed. 1922)
- Hermann von Helmholtz. Schriften zur Erkenntnistheorie (Publishers: Moritz Schlick & Paul Hertz). Berlin: Springer 1921[15]
- Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre. Berlin: Verlag von Julius Springer 1918 (2nd edition 1925)[16]
- Kritizistische oder empiristische Deutung der neuen Physik?, in: Kant-Studien, 26, 1921, p. 96-111[17]
- Einsteins Relativitätstheorie. In: Mosse Almanach, 1921, S. 105-123.[18][19]
- Erleben, Erkennen, Metaphysik, in: Kant-Studien, 31, 1926, p. 146-158[20]
Vom Sinn des Lebens, in: Symposion. Philosophische Zeitschrift für Forschung und Aussprache, Jg. 1, 1927, p. 331-354[21]
- Fragen der Ethik. Vienna: Verlag von Julius Springer 1930[14]
Gibt es ein Materiales Apriori?, 1930
- "Die Wende der Philosophie". Erkenntnis. 1: 4–11. 1930. doi:10.1007/BF00208605.
- "Über das Fundament der Erkenntnis". Erkenntnis. 4: 79–99. 1934. doi:10.1007/BF01793485.
- Unanswerable Questions, 1935
- Meaning and Verification, 1936
- Gesammelte Aufsätze 1926-1936. Vienna: Gerold & Co. 1938
- Die Probleme der Philosophie in ihrem Zusammenhang. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Verlag 1986
- Moritz Schlick Gesamtausgabe. Vienna/New York: Springer Verlag 2006. — Almost complete author copy of Vol. I/1, I/2, I/3, I/5, I/6
Notes
- Ted Poston, "Foundationalism" (Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
- Hans Günther Ruß, Wissenschaftstheorie, Erkenntnistheorie und die Suche nach Wahrheit. Stuttgart, Kohlhammer Verlag 2004, p. 71.
- Thomas Oberdan, Protocols, Truth and Convention, Rodopi, 1993, p. 110.
- B. F. McGuinness (2013). Moritz Schlick. pp. 336–7. Once again, one has to understand Schlick's world conception, which he took over from Schopenhauer's world as representation and as will. … “To will something” – and here Schlick is heavily influenced by Schopenhauer –
- Schlick, Moritz; Stadler; Wendel (2009). Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre. 1 (Kritische Gesamtausgabe ed.). Germany: Springer-Verlag. ISBN 978-3-211-32768-5.
- Biography Archived 2016-03-04 at the Wayback Machine at Vienna University
- Erkenntnis vol. 3, 1932/33. English: translated by David Rynin (PDF). Retrieved 2013-03-11.
- Stadler, Friedrich (2001). Documentation: The Murder of Moritz Schlick, in: Friedrich Stadler (ed.). The Vienna Circle. Studies in the Origins, Development, and Influence of Logical Empiricism. Vienna, New York: Springer. pp. 866–909. ISBN 978-3-211-83243-1.
- Silverman, Lisa (2012). Becoming Austrians: Jews and culture between the World Wars. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 60–65. ISBN 978-0-19-979484-3.
- Lotz-Rimbach, Renata (2009). Mord verjaehrt nicht: Psychogramm eines politischen Mordes, in: Friedrich Stadler, Fynn Ole Engler (eds.). Stationen: dem Philosophen und Physiker Moritz Schlick zum 125. Geburtstag. Vienna, New York: Springer. pp. 81–104. ISBN 978-3-211-71580-2.
- Csendes, Peter (2006). Wien: Von 1790 bis zur Gegenwart. Vol. 3. Vienna: Boehlau. pp. 499f. ISBN 978-3-205-99268-4.
- Stadler, Friedrich (1997). Die andere Kulturgeschichte am Beispiel von Emigration und Exil der oesterreichischen Intellektuellen 1930-1940, in: Rolf Steininger, Michael Gehler (eds.). Oesterreich im 20. Jahrhundert. Ein Studienbuch in zwei Baenden. Von der Monarchie bis zum Zweiten Weltkrieg. Wien, Köln, Weimar: Boehlau. pp. 535–553. ISBN 978-3-205-98310-1.
- Malina, Peter (1988). Tatort: Philosophenstiege, in: Michael Benedikt, Rudolf Burger (eds.). Bewusstsein, Sprache und Kunst. Vienna: Boehlau. pp. 231–253.
- Reprinted in Vol. I/3 of the Moritz Schlick Gesamtausgabe
- Editors' preface reprinted in Vol. I/5 of the Moritz Schlick Gesamtausgabe, p.255-264
- Reprinted as Vol. I/1 of the Moritz Schlick Gesamtausgabe
- Reprinted in Vol. I/5 of the Moritz Schlick Gesamtausgabe, p.223-250
- Contribution to a competition of Scientific American; for background information see p.31ff in: Fynn Ole Engler, Moritz Schlick und Albert Einstein, MPI for the History of Science, 2006
- Reprinted in Vol. I/5 of the Moritz Schlick Gesamtausgabe, p.157-178
- Reprinted in Vol. I/6 of the Moritz Schlick Gesamtausgabe, p.33-56
- Reprinted in Vol. I/6 of the Moritz Schlick Gesamtausgabe, p.99-128
References
- Edmonds, David and John Eidinow. Wittgenstein's Poker. New York: HarperCollins, 2001.
- Fynn Ole Engler, Mathias Iven. Moritz Schlick. Leben, Werk und Wirkung. Berlin: Parerga 2008. (in German)
- Schlick, Moritz. Positivism and Realism. Originally appeared in Erkenntnis 111 (1932/33); translated by Peter Heath and reprinted in Moritz Schlick: * Philosophical Papers, Volume II (1925–1936) from Vienna Circle Collection, edited by Henk L. Mulder (Kluwer, 1979), pp. 259–284.
Further reading
- Holt, Jim, "Positive Thinking" (review of Karl Sigmund, Exact Thinking in Demented Times: The Vienna Circle and the Epic Quest for the Foundations of Science, Basic Books, 449 pp.), The New York Review of Books, vol. LXIV, no. 20 (21 December 2017), pp. 74–76.
External links
- Moritz Schlick @ Wikipedia
- Schlick : Epistemology and Modern Physics
- Moritz Schlick research department at Rostock University